On failure

fullsizeoutput_207I’ve always found it a tad bombastic when I hear people say there is nothing in their life they regret. The fact of the matter is that none of us make it out of here without a few self-inflicted wounds. To regret one’s own failures is not a sign of a life not well lived. To the contrary, there is great depth of character to be formed by staring deep into our errors, learning from them, and, eventually, forgiving ourselves for them. This post hopes to offer some useful framing to help you work through the best way to respond to the mistakes you will inevitably make.

Of course, not all failures are equal – some cause momentary embarassment or frustration, while others can alter the entire course of a life. To find solace for our regrets we need to understand the difference between everyday idiocy and true catastrophe. I’ll pick each off one separately.

Everyday idiocy

We’ve all been there. Perhaps your mouth spoke before your brain had completed its due diligence, and now you look quite foolish. Or perhaps you unintentionally offended someone you just met. Or perhaps you made an obvious mistake at work, or on a test. Whatever it is, the self-commentary kicks in soon enough – this episode clearly proves that you are the most idiotic, deranged human that ever drew breath, and that you must be locked away for good.

At such times, the wise person would remember a simple truth – we are all barely evolved apes wrestling against the limited capacity of our pre-frontal cortex to cope with an environment that is very different from our original home in the savannah. It’s not that you are particularly brutish or stupid, it’s just that the job of getting through life when there are so many ways to go wrong is very hard.

Coping with everyday idiocy requires a healthy sense of how much weight should be placed on our negative inner voices. Much of the critical self-talk that follows when we make a mess of things is a distant echo of some of the less generous figures we have had to cope with throughout our lives – an unkind friend, a thoughtless teacher, a bully, an overly critical partner, or other such memorable sources of unhelpful input. Next time try to think about a gentler, more loving voice. Perhaps your mum. She doesn’t think you’re a fool, she thinks you’re a wonderful and charmingly human person, and she is right.

True catastrophe

It is true that there are some failures that cannot be brushed off so readily. Perhaps you’ve made a truly serious mistake professionally that has cost you your job or your reputation. Perhaps you’ve lost years of your life and all your savings as a result of a failed business venture. Or perhaps, despite your best efforts to keep it alive, a long-term relationship has failed and you are now left to pick up the pieces.

Such losses should not be trivialised. You will not wake up tomorrow and have forgotten that they ever occurred. Your life has now fundamentally changed. The hurt will last and a scar will form. But you will come out wiser, surer of who you are and what you value, and hopefully ready and willing to prevent those in your life from making the same mistakes as you.

In such situations, the wise person won’t play down what has happened. But they will remember the importance of resilience.

Someone once told me that resilience means being able to continually ask ‘what next?’ This has always stuck with me. One chapter of your life may have come to a close. But, and perhaps not yet but with time, you will turn the page and start your next journey stronger than before.

History is peppered with stories of massively succesful men and women who trod a long path of failure and disappointment before eventually reaching the summit. There is much comfort to be found in the stories of the likes of Thomas Edison, RH Macy, Walt Disney, JK Rowling, and many more. My personal favourite is Abraham Lincoln, who suffered a long list of political failures before eventually being elected President. He wrote the following words: “My great concern is not whether you have failed, but whether you are content with your failure”. That is resilience.

Ultimately, we are all incredibly fallible beings. An attitude of compassion, both to others and to yourself, and a willingness to look past failures and move forward is absolutely essential for making the most of your brief time on the planet.

To finish, below are some words of comfort from the always profound Emerson.

“Be not the slave of your own past. Plunge into the sublime seas, dive deep and swim far, so you will come back with self-respect, with new power, with an advanced experience that shall explain and overlook the old.”

On success

I met a traveller from an antique land, 
Who said—“Two vast and trunkless legs of stone
Stand in the desert. . . . Near them, on the sand,
Half sunk a shattered visage lies, whose frown,
And wrinkled lip, and sneer of cold command,
Tell that its sculptor well those passions read
Which yet survive, stamped on these lifeless things,
The hand that mocked them, and the heart that fed;
And on the pedestal, these words appear:
My name is Ozymandias, King of Kings;
Look on my Works, ye Mighty, and despair!
Nothing beside remains. Round the decay
Of that colossal Wreck, boundless and bare
The lone and level sands stretch far away

– Ozymandias, Percy Bysshe Shelley

greek-mythologiesOne of the most interesting social developments in western economies over the past two centuries has been the rise of the concept of meritocracy, where our status and wealth should follow directly from the extent of our talents and effort. Go back a few centuries and the fact that someone was a wealthy landowner would not be seen as a reflection of their capabilities or commitment, but simply their birth. Likewise, if someone was a peasant, that did not necessarily indicate a lack of aptitude – rather, it was their position at birth, and there were nearly no circumstances in which they could change that. Unfortunately (or fortunately), your prospects in life were mostly independent of your individual traits.

Meritocracy has been an incredible engine of social progress – we live in a far more economically mobile society than any before us, in which there is broad consensus that not only should we receive in proportion to what we contribute, but also that for the most part we do. Let’s put to the side whether this is empirically accurate (read here about why it’s not) – the fact is that we were all raised to believe we can be and do anything if we are talented and work hard.

And so enters in popular culture and popular wisdom the relatively modern notion of the ‘succesful’ person, and the topic of this blog. On first glance, it appears somewhat vaguely defined, and as the cliche goes ‘success’ means different things to different people. But I think if we are honest with ourselves there are really only a few archetypes of success we recognise in society. They are the kinds of people you would be particularly proud to introduce to your friends if you were hosting a dinner party – the professionally succesful businessman or entrepreneur, the celebrated artist or enetertainer, the string-pulling politician, the trophy-winning athlete, and perhaps one or two others. We would all love to be them, and perhaps many of us still believe, deep down inside, that one day we will.

Actually, the question I think we should be asking ourselves is ‘Do I really want to be succesful?’ Feels like an odd one to pose, and the received answer from popular wisdom is obvious. After all, an entire motivation industry has been built up over recent decades to help people ‘unlock’ their potential by learning from other heroes of the journey towards success. I constantly see articles appearing on my Facebook with titles like ‘Ten mental habits of succesful people’. The default position on the question is clear.

Unfortunately, as a species we are not particularly good at working out what we need to do (and not do) to make ourselves happy. Alain de Botton, in his (excellent) book ‘Consolations of Philosophy’, writes that we are like headache sufferers in Medieval Europe who, believing their symptoms to be due to an excess of air in the skull, had someone drill a small hole in their heads only to die shortly after from a brain aneurism. The treatment was disastrous because the understanding of the root cause was so flawed.

Ancient Greek philosopher Epicurus had an interesting take on what human happiness requires. Humans have basic necessities that must be met – food, shelter, clothing. Beyond this, Epicurus argued that the sources of happiness were quite straightforward: friendship – deep personal relationships with kindred spirits; freedom – to spend our time as we see fit in pursuit of our own passions; and reflection – on the world, and on the sources of our anxieties. Quite a simple formula really. Unfortunately, failing to recognise what it takes for us to be happy, we chase after all the wrong solutions.

Take the pursuit of money, for example. I suspect there are very few people who invest their lives accumulating wealth to purchase beautiful homes, vintage car collections, and haute couture out of a deep passion for craftsmanship. Rather, people spend conspicuously with the intention, conscious or perhaps subconscious, simply of demonstrating that they have the money to spend. Why would we do such a silly thing? Making money is hard work, after all!

Epicurus would tell us, perhaps, that we bought that Gucci handbag because we are lonely. We lack the validation we need from deep human relationships, so we look to inspire envy instead. If people want to be us, they will of course want to be friends with us, we tell ourselves. Perhaps the next time you see someone driving a Ferrari, sympathy may be a more appropriate response – a friend, not a Ferrari, was what they really needed.

Of course, there are parallel arguments for all the other wrong-headed ways we go about pursuing success in order to make ourselves happy. The celebrity who spends their life pursuing fame may have suffered more than you might expect.

The tragedy is that such pursuits not only fail to provide what we truly need to be happy, but may in fact take us further away from these things. A life spent pursuing money and fame is likely to leave us with few true friends, little freedom to do as we please, and perhaps less impetus to stop and think deeply about who we are and what we want from our short time on the earth.

Ozymandias – the poem at the beginning of this post – reminds us that even the greatest men will eventually be forgotten. Ultimately, our time here is brief, especially our young years.

All this is not to say that we should not bother trying to make the most of our talents. By all means, do your best and live with dedication. But hopefully it lends us a new perspective – to more thoughtfully evaluate our reasons for pursuing success, and perhaps to be kinder with ourselves when we don’t achieve what we set our hearts on.

I’ll finish with another lovely poem, this time from an octogenarian imparting a little bit of life wisdom.

If I had my life to live over again,
I’d make more mistakes next time.
I would relax.
I would limber up.
I would be sillier than I have been this trip.
I would take very few things seriously.
I would take more chances.
I would take more trips.
I would climb more mountains,
watch more sunsets,
and swim more rivers.
I would eat more ice cream
and less beans.
I would perhaps have more actual troubles,
but fewer imaginary ones.
You see, I’m one of those people who have been
sensible and sane.
Oh, I’ve had my moments
and if I had it to do over again,
I’d have nothing else.
Just moments, one after another,
instead of living so many years ahead each day.
I’ve been one of those people who never goes anywhere
without a thermometer, a hot water bottle,
a raincoat and a parachute.
If I had it to do over again,
I would go places and do things
and travel lighter than I have.
If I had my life to live over again,
I would go barefoot earlier in the spring
and stay that way later in the fall.
I would go to more dances.
I would ride more merry-go-rounds.
I would pick more daisies.

– I’d Pick More Daisies, Nadine Stair (aged 85)

On Individualism, Capitalism, and Ayn Rand

Objectivist1

Last year I was encouraged by a friend to read Any Rand’s classic and highly influential novel Atlas Shrugged. For those that are unfamiliar with the book, it is largely considered Rand’s most important novel, and was arguably one of the most influential pieces of thinking behind the resurrection of economic liberalism towards the latter end of the 20th Century, following the pervasiveness of Keynesianism in the post-war era. Indeed, one of Rand’s most passionate followers was Alan Greenspan, who chaired the US Federal Reserve from the mid-1980s to the mid-2000s, and was a key figure in the resurgence of market rationalism in the US over that period. Greenspan has on many occasions readily affirmed the strong influence Rand had on his intellectual development, and was in fact a close confidant of hers. But Rand’s influence was certainly more broad than this. For instance, her thinking was highly influential at the various conservative US think tanks that drove much of the liberalisation, privatisation, and deregulation in the West in the latter part of the 20th Century (including the deregulation of finance).

Whilst reviewing books is not really my forte, I felt that this was one book that was worth writing about. To begin with, I will give a brief overview of the book (with minimal spoilers!) and then try and summarise Rand’s philosophy, which she explores through the medium of fiction. I will then discuss what I like about it and what I agree with, and I will then offer a few thoughts on where I think Rand’s philosophy breaks down.

Atlas Shrugged is the story of a strike, set in mid-20th Century America. However, it is not a strike as we have come to imagine them. Rather, this is a strike of the productive elite – the men and women of great intellect who drive the economy and underpin the standard of living of the nation. The title of the book alludes to its key theme – when society begins to demand too much of this elite, expecting them to shoulder the wants of the whole world, the only response that is left to them is to shrug their obligations off, and to abandon the world to a collectivist/socialist dystopia with no productive capacity to feed itself. Frankly, this is about all you need to know of the story to understand her philosophy – Rand uses 1,100 pages of novel (in my version at least…) to explore a philosophy more than to write a particularly nuanced piece of fiction.

Rand coined the term ‘Objectivism’ for her particular philosophy, and defined it with four elements:
1. A metaphysics based on objective reality
2. An epistemology based purely on reason
3. An ethics of self interest
4. A politics of unfettered capitalism

This is the ‘technical’ side of it, but Rand summarised her philosopy neatly as follows:

“My philosophy, in essence, is the concept of man as a heroic being, with his own happiness as the moral purpose of his life, with productive achievement as his noblest activity, and reason as his only absolute.”

For Rand, man’s only obligation is to achieve his own desires by bending nature to his will. In her view, pity and compassion are tools employed by the weak against the strong in order to guilt the strong into putting the wants of others above the only rational objective for their lives – their own happiness. For Rand, the pursuit of self interest was not only the right order of things, but indeed the most moral way for man to live his life – to give to others what they don’t deserve was, in her view, immoral. Underpinning Rand’s view of the world was a strong belief in rationalism and reason as the only right forms of thought.

First, I will give credit where credit is due – Rand does makes some important points in her book.

Rand argues that you and I are not entitled to a certain standard of living just because we exist and because we were born into a certain country. I find myself agreeing with this, at least in principle. The jobs that we have exist because courageous and intelligent people were able to identify a need or discover a better way of doing things, and create an enterprise to achieve that. Likewise, what we consume, and the price at which we are able to consume it, are the products of this same entrepreneurialism. Of course, this doesn’t mean we are entitled to nothing just because we haven’t built our own enterprise. To the contrary, we are entitled to the economic value that we contribute to society through our labour (and whatever investments we have) – enterprise cannot operate on ideas and entrepreneurship alone. But Rand is correct in saying that our incomes and our standard of living do not simply appear out of nowhere (or some kind of mechanistic economy, as some academic economists seem to imagine exists) – they are the product of toil. I’m reminded of a great Einstein quote:

“Every day I remind myself that my inner and outer life are based on the labors of other men, both living and dead, and that I must exert myself in order to give in the same measure as I have received and am still receiving.”

All else equal, if I demand a standard of living above and beyond the value I volunteer to create through my effort, then I force someone to bear a load that is simply unfair for them to bear. Moreover, work is a fundamental part of who we are as human beings, and is key to our self-actualisation. If we choose not to push ourselves to our best, we not only opt for a lower standard of living but we also rob ourselves of the pride in a job well done and the knowledge that we have made the most of ourselves.

So much for the broad principle. However, I take exception to Rand’s philosophy, as borne out in Atlas Shrugged, for a few reasons. These are not collectively exhaustive – certainly, much more could be written on this book, and Rand’s philosophy in general, than I would care to write (and I’m sure you would care to read!). To me, these are just the most important shortcomings.

First, in Rand’s world there exists no imbalance of opportunity. Indeed, Rand mocks the idea of equality of opportunity, portraying it merely as another justification given by those who would impose their wants upon the productive and motivated in society. (I discuss inequality of opportunity in more depth here)

Second, Rand gives no consideration whatsover to the instances in which individuals pursuing their own economic interest do not generate efficient outcomes. For instance, anti-competitive behaviours (where firms solve not for their customers’ wants, but for the attainment of monopolistic market power – also known as ‘economic rents’) would simply never cross the mind of one of Rand’s heroes (in the story, such behaviours are reserved solely for those in bed with a highly corrupt government), and yet this is all too often what is observed, and is the reason we have competition watchdogs in all advanced economies. Likewise, principal-agency problems, where the managers of corporations solve for empire-building and their personal interest (as opposed to the company’s interest) are completely ignored in Rand’s world, in which corporations are run by founders or their heirs (in contrast to the vast majority of corporations in the real world).

Third, and perhaps most importantly, Rand seems to suggest that it is only financial gain that can bring happiness to an individual. Rand presents a twisted and frankly quite disturbing view of romantic love, in which attraction is based partly on acceptance of my own individual worth and partly on some kind of natural attraction to any character that embodies Rand’s ideals. Rand seems to flatly reject the possibility of familial love (for those heroes in Atlas Shrugged who do have families, they are portrayed as parasitic and manipulative, rather than a source of joy). For the rest of society, all relationships are based on the ‘trader principle’ – other human beings are not part of a collective identity and shared humanity, but rather are a means to better advancing one’s own financial ends. At best, one might respect the competence of another human being. However, one would certainly never find joy in the happiness of others. Again, strangely, the only exception Rand seems to permit is if a character subscribes to her own philosophy. The general point is that Rand, while celebrating the achievement of man’s happiness as the ultimate end, seems to forbid the possibility that man might achieve happiness through anything other than financial gain and, perhaps more importantly, a dogged adherence to her worldview.

Together, these three examples illustrate a broader issue, which is that the arguments put forward in Atlas Shrugged lack sophistication and nuance, permit no exceptions, and give no ground on the potential failings of markets. If you’ll permit me to get on my hobby horse for a moment, this kind of ‘all or nothing’ view unfortunately seems to be the way many who are economically right-of-center argue. While progressives have largely ‘come to the party’ on market forces, accepting the failings of socialist systems, the right has not gravitated towards the centre for many decades, and indeed in recent years has gravitated back towards free market extremism.

In terms of the literature itself, there is one final comment I would make. The reason, in my view, that Rand is so effectively able to present a simplistic and one-sided view of humanity is that she employs the medium of fiction. The great irony here is that Rand herself argued that only reason and rational argument can form the basis of any belief. Yet she makes her argument appear compelling by embedding it in a story in which all ‘evidence’ leads irrefutably to support for her conclusions, leaving no room for doubt. The issues I have raised above are only some of the examples of ways in which observations of the real world (which are the most important test of an economic argument) undermine much of what Rand proposes. Perhaps the more aggregious sin in Atlas Shrugged is that Rand repeatedly builds a ‘straw man’ argument of all those who disagree with her (that is, a false representation of an opponent’s argument) in order to delegitimise any and all points against the total devolution of the economy to unfettered capitalism and the dogged pursuit of material self interest – progressives are presented as nothing more than “looters” who seek to ride off the productive efforts of others. I am no philosopher, but even I know that such methods of argument are disingenuous and frowned upon.

To summarise, my conclusion on Atlas Shrugged is that Ayn Rand effectively draws attention to a few principles that are broadly right – the inherent virtue of hard work and dedication (and their importance in self-actualisation), and the notion that, all else equal, we should not expect society to bestow a certain standard of living on us simply because we are unwilling to work for our due. However, Rand takes these principles and converts them into a fundamentalist philosophy and politics that not only offers no room for complexity or subtlety, but also portrays anyone who offers arguments to the contrary as manipulative and immoral. The fact that she has had such a strong influence on economic and political thinking today makes Atlas Shrugged an especially dangerous text. For this reason alone, it is well worth the read.

Should we pay nonprofit workers as much as for-profit workers?

 

Charity payThis blog post will tackle the perhaps controversial topic of whether those who work in the nonprofit sector should receive the same remuneration as their counterparts in for-profit roles. My short answer is no – that to some extent those who work in nonprofit roles should in fact be paid less than those in for-profit roles. However, what I hope to do is systematically lay out why the existing gap is far too large – in fact, so large that it not only penalises those who work in these roles and those disadvantaged members of our society who rely on the work of the nonprofit sector, but also that it traps the sector in a self-reinforcing cycle of underfunding and lower social impact.

Firstly, let’s tackle the question of whether or not the earnings of those in the nonprofit sector should be less than those in the for-profit sector. In economics there’s a concept known as ‘motivated agents’. In contrast to early classical economics, this theory argues that financial compensation is not the only force that drives people to work, and that there are situations in which people are in fact rewarded by the very nature of the work they do. Entrepreneurs, artists, and those who work in nonprofits are all classic examples of this. Suppose, for argument’s sake, that in the for-profit sector my work is worth $50 an hour (assume that I am willing to work for this rate, and that I get zero additional satisfaction from the job itself). Now suppose that I have an alternative job available to me in the non-profit sector that offers me $25 an hour. Should I take this job? Well it depends. Say I’m a ‘motivated agent’, and that working in a job that contributes directly to positive social outcomes is equivalent to $30 an hour to me in financial gain. Then yes, I should, because the non-profit job is effectively offering me the equivalent of $55 an hour in remuneration. So long as such people exist, the non-profit sector is able to compete in the labour market for the same pool of talent while offering lower financial remuneration. And it absolutely should make use of this fact – in the same way that for-profit firms want to keep labour costs down in order to maximise profits, the nonprofit sector should want to keep labour costs down in order to maximise the social impact it is able to generate with each dollar of donations.

Now let’s suppose our model nonprofit sector needs two employees (to keep it very simple, imagine it’s just one firm), and suppose it continues to offer $25 an hour. For argument’s sake suppose that there are three potential employees in the labour market. I can earn $50 an hour in the for-profit sector and value work in the nonprofit sector at $30 an hour, while Person X can also earn $50 per hour in the for-profit sector and values work in the nonprofit sector at $24 an hour. Person Y, however, is half as productive as myself and Person X, and so can only earn $25 in the for-profit sector; suppose that they receive no value from working the non-profit sector. In this situation, myself and Person Y take jobs in the non-profit sector, and Person X does not.

Can you see what the problem with this situation is? Let’s assume that an employee’s productivity in the for-profit sector is the same as their productivity in the nonprofit sector. Suppose myself and Person X produce 100 units of social impact per hour of work in the nonprofit sector, which implies Person Y produces 50 units of social impact. When the nonprofit sector offers a rate of $25 an hour (with a total labour cost of $50 per hour), it therefore is able to produce 150 units of social impact (this translates to 3 units of social impact for every dollar spent). If, however, the nonprofit sector had offered a rate of $26 per hour, it would have employed myself and Person X and been able to produce 200 units of social impact for a total labour cost of $52 (corresponding to roughly 4 units of social impact per dollar spent). Because this model nonprofit sector has underspent on labour, half of its workforce is competent motivated agents, while the other half are simply incompetent workers who could never have earned a higher rate in the for-profit sector anyway. By offering a greater wage the nonprofit sector would have been able to effectively compete for talented workers and ultimately achieve a greater social impact per dollar spent.

I’ve used this example, while obviously extremely simplified, to demonstrate the following logic: while the nonprofit sector should be able to pay below the market rate due to the presence of motivated agents, if it pays too little the result is a mixture of motivated agents and less competent staff, which in turn depresses the per dollar social impact of the sector

So why wouldn’t the nonprofit sector just increase wages, assuming they are rational? Unfortunately, I don’t think it’s all that easy. People give to the nonprofit sector because they value positive social outcomes (if you want more of an exploration of this issue, have a read of the other posts on my blog on this topic). In effect, then, people are ‘buying’ social impact from the nonprofit sector. If a product is lower quality, you pay less. If the nonprofit sector is not able to generate as much social impact, it receives less donations. It is therefore able to offer less financial remuneration to its staff, which in turn maintains a lower social impact from the sector. This trap is reinforced by two facts: firstly, it can be difficult for the average donor to tell when a charity has increased its social impact; secondly, donors have historically expected remuneration to be quite low in the nonprofit sector (probably because of the role that the church, which produces many highly motivated agents, played in the initial formation of the sector).

Even the most cursory glance at the numbers suggests that the nonprofit sector on the whole simply does not compete for the same talent pool as the for-profit sector. In his TED talk (which I highly recommend), social entrepreneur Dan Pallotta observes that 10 years after business school the median remuneration for a Stanford MBA graduate is $400,000. At the same time, the median remuneration for the CEO of a hunger charity in the US is roughly $80,000. Such charities would only be able to compete for those minds if there was a sufficiently large number of MBA grads that valued social impact against financial remuneration at a ratio greater than 4:1, which seems extremely unlikely. Instead, our best management minds go on to the for-profit sector.

Somehow, we as a society are okay with people making a lot of money for themselves and doing nothing to help the disadvantaged (or advancing causes such as environmental protection or cures for cancer), while those who earn a competitive salary doing good are seen as social parasites – to me, this seems very backwards. It is worth keeping this in mind next time you hear yourself or someone else complaining about the ‘administrative expenses’ of charities, rather than working out where your money can do the most good.

Competing charities – what does that mean, and when is it a problem?

I wrote a post on this blog a couple of months back now that tackled some of the myths and misunderstandings about the charity sector that I frequently came across while researching for my honours thesis. As a kind of sequel to that post I decided it would be a good idea to delve a bit deeper into the notion of competition between charities. If you haven’t already, I would strongly recommend reading this post in conjunction with my previous post on the charity sector.

I’m a big believer in always having a ‘first principles’ understanding of an issue –  that is, starting at a kind of logical ground zero. The human brain is very good at taking short cuts – or, more technically, using ‘heuristics’ – to try to reach an understanding of something. The best way to get around this is to start at square one.

So, what is square one here? I think the first question that needs to be asked when we’re trying to understand the nature and desirability of competition between charities is to understand why we would want more than one charity for any given cause (something that I touched on briefly in my earlier post). For instance, what’s the benefit of having Oxfam if we already have World Vision? There are, of course, many different reasons why we may have more than one charity. If we stick with the previous example then, for starters, Oxfam and World Vision were founded in separate countries in a period where communication and the flow of resources was notably less globalised than it is today. Indeed, it’s not hard to think of lots of reasons why multiple charities may form. We have religious charities and we have secular charities. We have ‘branded’ charities (for instance, celebrity charities) and we have charities established to focus on a certain niche area that particularly concerns their founders. And so on.

But why we would have many charities is not the same question as why we would want many charities. (The first question is definitely interesting from a regulation perspective, but not so important here). The first proposition I’d like to make is that having multiple charities increases the efficiency of the ‘production’ of charity (if you’ll let me use that terminology). There’s a phrase in economics called ‘X-inefficiency’. The phrase was basically developed to explain the fact that companies just don’t operate as efficiently as economists’ models expect them to. Businesses are complex entities made up of complex people whose incentives are rarely exactly the same as the companies they work for. This is as true for the charity sector as it is for the private sector. But here’s the important point: in the private sector, competition for dollars forces firms to stamp out X-inefficiency, or else risk losing customers to competitors who can deliver the same things more cheaply or at a higher standard. This logic carries across to the charity sector. Oxfam cannot afford to consistently operate less efficiently than World Vision, or whatever other development NGO prospective donors weigh them against, because donors would sooner or later realise that every dollar they give Oxfam delivers less results in the cause they care about than if they were to allocate that dollar to another charity. (Quick aside – obviously none of this should be taken as an assessment of the relative merit of these charities/causes). Of course, the diffusion of this information may take a bit longer in the charity sector as ‘social impact’ is a more opaque concept than price. But the logical foundation is the same.

Wait a second. Charities don’t actually compete that way, right? Don’t they compete using fundraising? This was a comment I got from many people in response to my previous blog post on charities, and I can definitely understand where they are coming from. But I think there’s a deeper conceptual layer here that needs to be properly understood. I don’t buy a particular brand of clothes because of their marketing campaign. Instead, I buy that brand because the marketing campaign has convinced me that the product looks better/feels better/is better/is cheaper/whatever. Again, the logic is the same for charities. Oxfam’s advertising campaign is intended to convince me that giving to Oxfam is the best use of my discretionary dollar. The fundraising effort is ultimately just a mode of communication – the actual competition is occurring at a deeper level.

The potential social benefit of fundraising is that it fosters competition between charities – ultimately, it is difficult for a charity to consistently persuade people that it does the best work if that’s clearly not the case. By definition, then, fundraising is socially beneficial if the increased value it produces through improved efficiency exceeds the cost of fundraising. At an aggregate level, I think this is a very low bar which is easily met, and probably well exceeded, by what we actually observe from the fundraising activities of charities.

In fact, I think I’m of the view that the charity sector should probably spend substantially more than it presently does on fundraising (though there’s been no empirical study of this to date, so it’s just a hunch). This is only in part because of the benefits I just mentioned in terms of increased competition. The other really important point to make is that a charity is not just competing for some fixed pie of total charitable donations. Certainly, some people have a fixed giving budget each year, but this is neither indicative at an aggregate level nor is it constant over the longer-term. Rather, when you think about it, the charity sector as a whole is actually competing for a slice of total discretionary spending in the economy. When I decide how much of my money to allocate towards charitable giving I am weighing up how much ‘utility’ (economics jargon for something like happiness or satisfaction) I expect I will get from giving to my preferred causes against how much utility I will get from spending my money on other stuff. My expectation of the relative utility I will get from these different destinations for my money is strongly connected to the messaging I have been exposed to, which includes marketing from the charity sector. In other words, World Vision is not just competing with Oxfam, but it’s actually also competing with Myer, Apple, JB Hi-Fi, and the numerous other companies who want to trade you your money for some purported increase in your happiness.

In my own experience, giving $100 away to a cause I care about brings me far more joy and lasting satisfaction than buying a new pair of jeans. Perhaps money can buy some measure of happiness – you just have to find the right cause.

How Economics Made Me a Progressive: Part II – The Homo Economicus Prescription

Image

At the same time as many economists ignore the potential role of pro-market ideology in distorting their empiricism, many also ignore the prescriptive role of their models. In particular, I would like to use this second part to talk about the role of self-interest in society.

The notion of self-interest as societally beneficial was codified in Smith’s Wealth of Nations, one of the most influential books in all of economics. Smith famously argued that “It is not from the benevolence of the butcher, the brewer, or the baker that we expect our dinner, but rather from their regard to their own interest.” That is, Smith argues in his book that the material things we enjoy are delivered to us precisely because people pursue their own interests. Our needs and wants are met simply as a result of mutually advantageous transactions, as opposed to acts of charity.

Smith has since been used as a clarion call for those who believe in conservative economic policy, arguing that, in the immortal words of Gordon Gekko, “Greed is Good.” However, as is often the case with great thinkers, Smith’s writings don’t seem to be all that well understood among the general population (and sometimes even amongst those with some education in economics). One will not find in The Wealth of Nations any sort of vindication for economic behaviour that interests one person at the direct expense of another. Indeed, Smith’s understanding of the role of individual interest in advancing society becomes a much more elaborate tapestry when we also look at his other famous book, The Theory of Moral Sentiments. Tellingly, Smith writes in this book that

“How selfish soever man may be supposed, there are evidently some principles in his nature, which interest him in the fortune of others, and render their happiness necessary to him, though he derives nothing from it, except the pleasure of seeing it.”

In other words, Smith believed that there was something fundamental in human nature that meant that, even though we may seem to be concerned primarily with our own interest, we are not content to see others in a state of hardship. Either Smith held two contradictory ideas about our pursuit of self-interest, or he did not believe it was advantageous for man to pursue his interests to the detriment of others. I am of the opinion that Smith was not an advocate for self-interest in the way it has come to be understood within economics.

Self-interest reached its current zenith in economics due to the introduction of game theory, which was brought to the discipline by John Nash. Game theory is at its core simply a way of modeling human interactions which says that people take into consideration other people’s optimal choices when making their own decision. Behind this model, however, is a deeper statement about how humans behave. Effectively, humans are modeled to be pitted against one another. Game theory accepts that there are circumstances in which interests may coincide. However, the world is essentially modeled as every man and woman for themselves.

John Nash was a brilliant mathematician. He was also a paranoid schizophrenic, and in his autobiography he describes substantial parts of his work as “delusionally influenced”. For this reason, while I am awed by Nash’s logical prowess, I find it hard to accept the characterisation of human behaviour that sits behind much of game theory. (If you are interested, Adam Curtis’ documentary series The Trap, in which he interviews Nash, is very good. In it, Nash speaks quite openly of his doubts about how he modeled human behaviour).

At the same time, the data confronts the portrait of human nature that is painted by game-theoretic models based on pure self-interest. The Trust Game, The Dictator Game, and the Ultimatum Game are three types of experiments that were developed in order to examine whether humans actually tend to behave according to pure self-interest (for brevity I won’t describe the experimental set-up, though it is quite easy to find with a quick Google search). Tellingly, humans consistently do not conform to the predictions of these models, and instead exhibit a tendency to ensure that both participants in the experiment receive some kind of advantageous outcome.

Anecdotally, I’m sure you can see this in your own life. It’s the off feeling you get when you decide to pursue a course of action that benefits you but harms another. It’s the simple fact that you would prefer to live in a world where other people did not suffer absolute poverty. Basic observations such as these suggest that your personal preferences consist of more than simply your narrow self-interest.

From an evolutionary perspective, this makes perfect sense. Homo sapiens have been so amazingly successful as a species not because of our physical prowess, but because we have sufficient cognitive capacity to cooperate in large groups. This is largely a result of our capacity for ‘fictive language’ (the ability to develop narratives to understand the world and ourselves), which means we have been far better at forming communities than other species in the great ape family. There is something primal and fundamental within us that recognises the importance of coexistence.

It is interesting to observe that there are two groups of people who have a tendency to behave in experiments according to the prescriptions of pure self-interest. The first is verifiable psychopaths. The second is economists. This fact is kind of funny, but I also find it slightly disturbing. The reason is that it suggests that people who are exposed to the notion that pure self-interest is proper and natural human behaviour actually come to operate according to that principle. This suggests that economics has gradually morphed into more than simply an analytical discipline. It has become a kind of prescription for human behaviour.

Orthodox economists, seeing the pursuit of pure self-interest as normal and healthy for society, go on to characterise it as exactly that. The concept and the rhetoric filters through to our political leaders, into our popular culture, and ultimately on to us. However, if we are ever to effectively tackle the great challenges we face as a species, we are going to need to move away from a narrow focus on our individual wants and rediscover our immense potential for cooperation.

How Economics Made Me a Progressive: Part I – Empiricism or Ideology

“An economist is someone who sees something that works in practice and wonders if it will work in theory.”

Ronald Reagan

Image

This is a blog post about why I don’t believe a thorough understanding of economics compels one to identify as an economic conservative. I have noticed over the past few years that there is a trend among my generation to identify as ‘socially progressive but economically conservative’. I suspect that there are a few reasons why this label has become particularly popular, such as the steady transmutation of many identifying as ‘working class’ into an ‘aspirational class’. But I believe that one of the reasons is that it is generally assumed that anyone who knows anything about economics understands that a laissez-faire market, with a very small number of exceptions in cases of clear market failure, is the way to a prosperous society. I would like to put forward a case as to why developing a fuller understanding of economic forces actually lends itself equally well to a more progressive perspective on the economy. This is largely a reflection on my own experience of completing a degree in economics.

I would, however, like to preface this blog with the following. I don’t believe that a proper understanding of how markets operate (and how people operate within markets) necessitates a progressive outlook either. A number of my fellow economists are much more intelligent than I am and have developed a strong conviction that the free operation of the market is the means to better our society. It is simply my intention to challenge the preconception that one cannot have a complete grasp of the economy and simultaneously believe in progressive economic policy. My personal view is that, once you have developed a sufficient knowledge of how the economy operates, it is more likely to be the values formed elsewhere in your life that determine your political persuasion, as opposed to economics itself.

For the sake of clarity, I see ‘progressive economic policy’ as having three key elements: a significant redistribution of income; an important role for government in intervening in markets; and legislative backing for collective bargaining to have a role in determining the relative returns to labour and capital.

I’d like to break this topic down into two blog posts. Firstly, in this post I will talk about the important distinction that needs to be drawn between empiricism and ideology within economics, and the ramifications this has for a variety of important and topical economic issues. In the next post, I will talk about the role of economics as a prescriptive discipline, rather than simply an analytical one. These mightn’t seem like the most interesting themes on the surface, but I promise that if you read on you’ll find some pretty juicy stuff. I’ve split this topic into two posts to make it more digestible, but I would encourage you to read both posts before making up your mind on the topic.

Now, after that lengthy preface…

Economics as a discipline likes to frame itself as free of value judgments and normative biases. However, I would like to suggest that this is frequently not the case. Instead, economics has come to develop a kind of unquestioning faith in the market, and this frequently comes up against its desire to be a purely empiricist discipline (where empiricism refers to the idea that knowledge is chiefly derived from an interpretation of the sensory experiences, hence prioritizing the role of observation). I’ll give three examples that show how, in my view, restoring empiricism to economics would lead the discipline to side with more progressive economic policy.

The first issue I’d like to talk about here is the way we understand who deserves what in terms of the annual output (equivalently, the annual income) of the economy. Since the days of Alfred Marshall, a famous economist in the late 19th and early 20th centuries, the dominant view within economics has been that people more or less get what they deserve. What do I mean by that? If you haven’t studied economics, this will probably seem complex, but bear with me. In the economics jargon, you receive the value of the marginal product from employing your resources at the point of market equilibrium. What I mean by this is basically that, as the orthodox view goes, if you give up your labour or your savings, you will more or less get the market value of putting those resources to use. This market value is simply how much of the product (or products) is made by employing your resources (given how much is already being used), multiplied by the market price. Hopefully you’re more familiar with how the market price is understood to be determined – the intersection of supply and demand – so for the sake of brevity I will leave that part out of this blog post.

This way of understanding who gets what in the economy is known as the Marginal Productivity Theory of Distribution. Big name, but I’ve given you the general gist of what it means above – someone who provides their labour (i.e. a worker) will get the equilibrium value of what they add to annual production, as will someone who provides their capital. I want to suggest that this theory, while mathematically elegant and tidy, is in fact a poor reflection of the reality.

Rather, I think a more accurate representation was given by David Ricardo, a classical economist who made his mark quite a few decades before Alfred Marshall. Ricardo modeled the returns to labour and capital as interdependent. Indeed, for Ricardo, profits were basically what was left over for the owners of capital after labour had been paid their wages. When you think about it carefully, this is a far better representation of what we observe in the market. Perhaps the Marginal Productivity Theory of Distribution would be useful if we lived in a world with perfectly competitive labour markets where anyone could move to any job anywhere without risk of significant loss and a very large number of firms actively competed for each others’ workers. But that is just not the world we live in. If we exclude collective bargaining, firms (and, thus, the owners of capital) have nearly all of the bargaining power when determining wages. This means that workers will simply receive as little as the firms are able to pay them.

(I won’t go into the theories about where the price of labour then comes from, but let it suffice to say that I think Adam Smith’s theory on this is actually the most convincing that I’ve come across. Smith suggests that wages are benchmarked against the minimum socially acceptable standard of living at the time, and then adjustments are made for things like the desirability or complexity of the work and conditions in the particular labour market in question).

Why is this important? Isn’t this all just very theoretical? This issue actually has some very important practical applications. In particular, it suggests that there is no reason that labour markets will naturally deliver what is fair to workers. It seems to have become increasingly popular to dislike labour unions over the last few decades. In Australia’s case they perhaps do have some things to answer for, though I think this changing attitude is probably more a result of the aforementioned shift from a ‘working class’ to an ‘aspirational class’. I would also add that I believe it is very important for unions to negotiate reasonably, recognising the various pressures businesses face in a global environment, and to avoid militancy. However, I do worry that if unions fade into insignificance workers will no longer be able to exercise the collective bargaining power that is required in order to ensure they receive a decent outcome from the wage negotiation process. Certainly, I do not buy the argument that individual enterprise bargaining will deliver an ‘efficient’ outcome – rather, it will simply allow firms to extract more value from their workers. For this reason, I think a more careful examination of how markets operate in practice should lead those with a knowledge of economics to reconsider the merits of those policies euphemistically known as ‘workplace flexibility’ policies.

The second issue I’d like to address in this post is inequality of opportunity. A paper that I studied during my degree examined the issue of intergenerational correlations in income – that is, the correlation between what parents earn and what their children earn. This correlation, which is typically used as a marker for income immobility in a country, was startlingly high. In the US, the figure is around 0.5 depending on the measure you use. (Australia has better income mobility with an intergenerational income correlation of 0.2 or, perhaps, between 0.2 and 0.3).

This figure means that, in the US, there is on average a 50% correlation between what a person earns and what their child will earn (or a 20-30% correlation in Australia’s case). This fact suggests that that, in the Western world, we do not have anything close to an equality of opportunity. Rather, the income of your parents is a significant determinant in how much you will earn.

Much conservative economic policy operates on the (probably unintentional) assumption that every person has the same opportunity to succeed in the economy so long as they apply the same effort. If this were truly the case, we would expect the earnings of parents to be an insignificant determinant in the earnings of their children. The reality, however, is that, for a variety of reasons, it is significantly more challenging for a person from a financially disadvantaged background to avoid economic hardship, irrespective of natural talent. This in turn sets up cycles of poverty for disadvantaged individuals at the same time as the wealthy enjoy cycles of prosperity. It is not my intention to try and solve this issue in this blog post, but my personal view is that continuing further along the spectrum towards means-based funding for education will probably be the most effective strategy.

The more general point, however, is that to form an opinion on economic policy based on the assumption that everybody has the same opportunities in the economy is to ignore economics’ call to empiricism and to instead embrace a blind faith in the efficiency of the market.

The third issue I’d like to explore in this first part is the idea of the ‘economic problem’. One of my favourite pieces of writing on economics is an essay by John Maynard Keynes – one of the most influential (and controversial) economists in the history of the discipline – titled ‘Economic Possibilities For Our Grandchildren’. Writing in 1930, Keynes was speculating on what the economy would look like, and what economic issues we would face, one hundred years hence.

One of the most insightful parts of the essay is when Keynes reframes the ‘economic problem’. Anyone who has studied any sort of introductory economics would have come across the conventional definition of the economic problem – how we are to allocate finite resources in order to satisfy people’s infinite wants.

This definition, however, did not simply fall from the sky. In fact, it is attributable to an economist named Lionel Robbins, who was at the London School of Economics around Keynes’ time. Keynes saw the economic problem differently. For him, there were two categories of wants. First, those things that people want as a result of their basic physiological requirements – to eat, to be sheltered, to be comfortable, and so on. Second, those things that people want precisely because they distinguish them from others. These merely cater to our selfish desire for superiority. If you pause for a moment, I’m confident you will be able to see both these categories at work in your own life. For Keynes, the second category of wants are, by definition, infinite – the greater the general level, the more people will want. However, as his essay argues, there is no natural reason why the first category of wants should be considered infinite. For Keynes, then, the real economic problem is simply humanity’s “struggle for subsistence”.

This struggle has been the defining focus of our species since its first days. However, Keynes suggests that, as a result of the explosion in technology in the latter part of the second millennium and the effect of continued, compounded economic growth over a number of centuries, the economic problem should become a relic of the past sometime in the 21st Century. In fact, in Keynes’ prediction, it was about 15 years from now – we are surprisingly close (though of course Keynes was not aiming for precision). If you pause to take stock, this is actually a huge proposition. Keynes is saying that our species will have reached an epoch clearly distinct from any in its entire history in which our physiological requirements no longer demand our constant attention.

We are continually bombarded by politicians and economists talking about the need to maintain solid economic growth. The question we should ask is ‘What for?’. Are we seeking to further grow our economy to ensure that our physiological needs are better met, or are we simply trying to speed up the treadmill of conspicuous consumption? It shouldn’t take more than a cursory thought to realise that, if we are increasing our national income in order to increase the production and consumption of goods that are used simply to try and position oneself above one’s neighbour, the effect on total wellbeing will be negligible. It is a kind of zero-sum game, in which one person’s happiness is another’s discontent.

So what’s the alternative? Just to be completely clear, I don’t believe in Socialism, as I think it has the same tendency to ignore empirical evidence as free-market fundamentalism. What I do believe, however, is that we need to change our attitude, and change our culture. In his essay, Keynes recognises the gravity of his prediction, and writes that:

“For the first time since his creation man will be faced with his real, his permanent problem – how to use his freedom from pressing economic cares, how to occupy the leisure, which science and compound interest will have won for him, to live wisely and agreeably and well.”

Instead of obsessing over increasing our consumption indefinitely, we should start to think about how we can use the opportunities this epoch will present us with to live as decent human beings that appreciate the physical comforts we have and assist those who don’t share in our abundance, to invest in relationships instead of assets, and to stop and appreciate beauty rather than to try and consume it. In this epoch, we can afford to have a generous, progressive economic policy – there will no longer be any great need to buy into the conservative economic agenda of perpetual growth.

Of course, I’m in no way wanting to suggest that further economic growth is undesirable (though, of course, there are serious environmental sustainability questions that we as a society need to consider). However, I believe it would simply be a tragic waste for us to allow the pursuit of wealth to continue to occupy the number one position in our lives. In his essay, Keynes depicts the love of money in a world beyond the economic problem in the following cutting way.

“The love of money, as a possession (as distinguished from the love of money as a means to the enjoyments and realities of life) will be recognised for what it is, a somewhat disgusting morbidity, one of those semi-criminal, semi-pathological propensities which one hands over with a shudder to the specialists in mental disease.”

Charities – the good, the bad, and the frequently misunderstood

Image

There was a popular TED talk doing the Facebook rounds last year by Dan Pallotta entitled ‘The way we think about charity is dead wrong’. Essentially, Pallotta, a veteran social entrepreneur, was presenting an argument that the modern nonprofit sector is severely constrained by the way society expects charitable organisations to operate. These preconceptions we hold, Pallotta argued, are often not based on careful thought, which leads to problematic outcomes for those trying to make a meaningful difference in the world.

The nature of the ‘charity market’ (if you’ll excuse that terminology) is a topic that has interested me for a number of years now. In fact, this was the topic of my recently completed economics thesis. For the last couple of months, I think I would have imploded if I had so much as thought about charities – I’m sure anyone who has written a thesis can relate to the feeling. Nevertheless, after a bit of a vacation from the topic, I thought it would be worthwhile to pen the observations and conclusions that arose from my research. Of course, as an economics thesis, what I wrote was about 90% mathematics (the other 10% being jargon). For those that are interested in the original thesis, I am happy to pass it on. Here, however, I offer a translation (to the best of my ability). To make it easily digestible, I have broken it down into a series of seven remarks.

Remark 1: Charities are far more important to our economy than you realise.

In the United States, the nonprofit sector represents a larger portion of GDP (an economy’s annual output) than agriculture. Here in Australia, the nonprofit sector is larger than agriculture, communications, and defence. I found this to be a particularly startling fact. Far from being a minor anomaly in the modern economy, the charity sector is actually a major employer and a major service provider for the most economically marginalized members of our local and global communities. I was quite taken aback by how little previous research there had been into the operation of the charity sector within the economics discipline. My suspicion is that many economists have not fully grasped the importance of nonprofit organisations (from a purely economic perspective, that is). With this in mind, it is perhaps less surprising that so little attention has been given to the question of what is desirable (or ‘efficient’) and what is undesirable (‘inefficient’) in terms of the activities of our charities.

Remark 2: When someone says to you “Charity X will spend Y% of your donation on fundraising”, they’re not quite on the money.

We have probably all heard someone say something like this in the past, and, if you’re guilty yourself, don’t be embarrassed – it seems to be a pretty common argument that’s based on a genuine concern. However, it also involves a formal logical error. In the economics jargon, it involves mistakenly conflating ‘marginal cost’ and ‘average cost’. In English, when I give a charity $100, it doesn’t matter how much was spent by that charity to get that $100 – that money has been spent, it’s gone! What matters is how the charity then goes and spends that $100 you have given it. You might find it helpful to think about it like a production line. In order for a charity to ‘produce’ $100 in donations, it needs to spend some money on fundraising (charities don’t just spend money on advertising for kicks – they do it because they need to generate money to fund their charitable activities).

(A more difficult question is whether the charity sector as a whole spends too much on fundraising as a result of competition for donations. For various reasons, this one is actually surprisingly complex, so I won’t tackle it in this blog post, though you’re welcome to send me an email if you’re really interested.)

Remark 3: When someone says to you “Charity X will spend Y% of your donation on administrative expenses”, your response should be “So what?”.

This is probably the most common misunderstanding when it comes to what is desirable and what is undesirable in our charity sector. Again, people raise this concern with the best of intentions, but again the thought process is not logically correct. Or, more accurately, it would be logically sound if every charity was producing a unit of ‘social impact’ in their respective area for exactly the same cost. What the hell does that mean? Consider this: a charity is not like a distribution company. They don’t take your dollar, carry it across the world, and give it someone who needs it. Rather, what they do is they take your dollar and use some kind of program to try and get the most social impact from it. A poverty alleviation charity takes your dollar and invests in clean water, education, or microfinance programs. A cancer research charity takes your dollar and hunts down the most promising line of research that seems to be presently underfunded. However, different charities have different strategies that cost different amounts. The real question, then, is not how much of the charitable dollar is going to ‘administration’ (which is a very poorly defined term anyway). Some programs are very complex to implement, and therefore have a large staff requirement, but their potential social impact can be very large too. Instead, the question should be, colloquially, how much bang do I get for my buck. That is, where will my dollar have the most impact.

Interestingly, the administrative expenses criticism is one that is often leveled at larger charities. However, perhaps surprisingly, all the empirical evidence to date indicates that larger charities actually have a lower administrative expenses ratio. That is, there are cost benefits to being a large charity (in the economics jargon, ‘increasing returns to scale’). Nonetheless, as I have noted above, this doesn’t mean that the actual per dollar impact of these charities is necessarily higher or lower.

Remark 4: Having multiple charities is a good thing.

One of the main issues I was interested in for my thesis was whether or not we actually need many charities. After all, if larger charities are more efficient, why not just have one super monopoly charity fighting poverty alleviation, one fighting homelessness, and so on. Of course, this is not what we observe in reality. In basically any charitable field you can think of there will be multiple charities operating. The answer is actually fairly simple: in the same way that having many firms in the for-profit sector encourages efficiency, having multiple charities competing for donations forces each charity to try and be the best. When I can choose between two nearly identical poverty alleviation charities, I will choose the one that is having the greatest impact. This forces both charities to compete by vying for the greatest social impact, lest they fail to maintain their donor base.

Remark 5: But we probably have too many charities already.

Great, so I should go and start my own charity to make the charity sector even more efficient, right? Probably not. I say ‘probably’ because there’s no available empirical data on this issue, and because there are theoretical exceptions anyway. Still, if you make a couple of basic assumptions (which I won’t go into here) the theory suggests that more than two charities competing over the same donor would be superfluous, and indeed cost-inefficient. And it’s not hard to think of two charities for pretty much every charitable cause. Moreover, there are charities that are formed for the wrong reasons (for instance, vanity, or, in the economics jargon, ‘ego rents’), which means it’s quite probable that we already have more charities than we need, unfortunately.

The exception, of course, is when you have a particularly unique method that you’re wanting to employ, or if you believe you will be particularly good at getting donations from people (e.g. you’re a celebrity). Otherwise, you’re almost certainly going to have more of an impact by donating to an existing charity and keeping your day job.

Remark 6: Donors are not like shareholders. They’re more like customers.

Often donors feel as though their contribution should buy them the right to tell a charity how to operate. This is kind of like me feeling like I have the right to tell Apple how to make their products because I choose to buy them. Charities do not have shareholders. Instead, charities have missions. To eradicate Malaria, AIDS, or Polio. To end absolute poverty. To fight for Americans’ right to own guns (yep, the NRA is a charity…). As a donor, you choose to give money to a charity because you actually benefit from the work they do in a roundabout sort of way. I want to live in a world in which children do not have their physical development stunted by malnutrition; I want to live in a world in which nobody suffers from diseases that are curable. These are my preferences, analogous to my preference for Verdelho over Semillon. Of course, these preferences are more fundamental to who I am as a person. But the point remains: I choose to give to a particular charity because I believe that doing so will help bring about the world I want to live in, and I believe that the particular charity I’m giving to is able to deliver the biggest social impact with my contribution. In the same way that a discerning customer must choose between multiple different products, a discerning donor must find the best charity to give their money to. The only difference is that the stakes are much, much higher.

Remark 7: Charities don’t already receive enough money.

As most of us see it, the work of making our world a better, kinder, and more sustainable one is already being done, and will continue to be done whether or not we give. The problem, however, is precisely that this is how most of us see it. We free ride off the donations of others, and tell ourselves that only the very rich need give a nontrivial portion of their income away. The irony, of course, is that we are the very rich, and if we don’t give abundantly, there’s no reason to expect that others will. The question that we have to ask ourselves, then, is what kind of world would we like to live in, and what are we willing to pay to make that world a reality. If you just try to take this ‘free riding’ element out of the equation for a moment, you may notice that living in a world that is free of abject hardship is far more important to you than many of the things that you allocate your money towards.

Somebody once told me that the answer to the question ‘How much should I give?’ is always the same: ‘More’.